Causal determinism—the
thesis that for any given time, a complete description of the state of
the world
at that time, together with
a complete statement of the laws of nature, entails every truth or state
of affairs
as to what happens after
that time.
Indeterminism—some
events do not have causes. Two types: metaphysical indeterminism is about
the
way the world is or is not,
and epistemological indeterminism is about our knowledge of the world.
These
two types may align, but
not necessarily.
Incompatibilist—accepts
that if causal determinism is true, there is no genuine human freedom.
Hard
Determinist—accepts that causal determinism is true, and thus there
is no genuine freedom.
Libertarian—accepts
that if causal determinism is true, there is no genuine human freedom.
However, causal determinism is false, thus there might be or is human freedom.
Compatibilist—denies
that if causal determinism is true, there is no genuine freedom.
Soft
Determinist—accepts causal determinism but denies that there is no
genuine human freedom.
Fatalism—1. There
exists a set of statements describing everyone’s future behavior all of
which are now
true (even if we don’t know
them) and 2) since these statements are now true, the behavior they describe
is unavoidable—people cannot
do other that what they will do. A fatalist need not be a causal determinist
because there may be uncaused
events in the future.
Forking Paths Model versus
the Deterministic Model—the forking paths reflect a freedom of choice,
i.e,
at each choice one can go
either of two ways. The deterministic model does not have these forks
and
thus is best represented
as a single path in one direction.
Consequence Argument—If
determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences of the laws of
nature
and events in the remote
past. But it is not up to us what went on before we were born, and neither
is it up
to us what the laws of nature
are. Thus, the consequences of these things (including our present acts)
are
not up to us.
Moral Responsibility—The
consequence argument shows that if things are not up to us, neither are
the
consequences of them. If
determinism is true, then we are not morally responsible for our actions—because
they are not up to us, nor
are we responsible for the consequences. If determinism is false, we may
be
morally responsible because
our actions may be up to us and we may responsible for some consequences.
INTEPRETATION:
I take Epictetus to have
a unique position, one like a modern day philosopher, Harry Frankfurt.
Epictetus
wants to argue that determinism
can be true, yet one is still morally responsible in some instances.
Frankfurt argues through
a higher-order account of volitions that is quite amenable to Epictetus.
There
are at least two orders
of desire, first-order and second-order. First order desires, “I am hungry;
I want to
go home, etc..” Second order
desires, “I desire to want to eat; I desire to want to go home.” Thus,
second
order desires are about
first-order desires. Someone has a desire of the second-order either:
1) when he wants
simply to have a certain desire.
2) when he
wants a certain desire to be his will.
Frankfurt calls #2, a second-order
volition—a desire that can lead someone to action. A person who
enjoys freedom of the will
means that he is free to want what he wants to want. It is in securing
the
conformity of his will to
his second-order volitions, then, that a person exercises freedom of the
will.
When the will and second-order
volitions do not align, a person feels the lack of the freedom.
The enjoyment of a free
will means the satisfaction of certain desires—desires of the second or
of
higher-orders—whereas its
absence means their frustration
Back to Epictetus. He is
constantly concerned with aligning his will with the plan of nature, see
4,
29, 31, and 49. Yet notice,
he often mentions things that are up to us, and things that are not. You
can choose how the externals
affect you; thus, it seems that you are not completely determined in
all respects. You can be
morally responsible for your actions when they don’t comport with nature.
The implicit premise here
for Epictetus is that living a virtuous life is one that aligns with the
function
and goal of nature. Thus
if you are not aligning your life with nature, you are not living a virtuous
life.
I think Epictetus is best
described as a compatibilist—we are both free and determined, but not in
the same respects.
When our will aligns with nature, we are free, when it does not, we are
not.
Lecture 5: An Aid to Understanding
the Free Will/Determinism Debate
Instructor: Scott Dixon
From our readings in Epictetus,
we know that some things are up to us or under our control, and some
things are not up to us,
or not under our control. Translating this into the terminology of the
Free Will
handout would result in
something like the following:
If every single thing is not under our control, we call that causal determinism.
If every single thing is under our control, we call that libertarianism.
If some things are under our control and some things are not, we call that compatibilism.
If some things are under
our control or some things are not, we call that incompatibilism.
One or
the other must be true or they must both be false.
The Paradise Island Scenario
One of the main implications
of this scenario is to show that we may have an appearance of free will,
yet all of our actions are
determined. Notice the shift in perspectives: from the subjective perspective
you wouldn’t know but from
an objective perspective, i.e. a God’s eye view, you would know.
A few questions to think about:
1. Do you think it is possible
to have an illusion of free will, yet be determined much like the
Paradise
Island scenario?
2. If lacking free will on PI bothers you, what value is missing? Choice, the ability to be self-directed or ?
3. Is there something defective
in the relationships on PI? For example, what would it mean for someone
to be
your ‘friend’ if all of the relationships are determined?
4. How would your conception
of yourself change if you knew you had no free will? Or would it? For
example,
if you were not free to choose your spouse what would that say about what
you want?
5. Does Epictetus’ general
idea that some things are up to us and others are not convince you that
compatibilism
might be true or the correct formulation?