DEFINITIONS:
death—the cessation
of life. This includes many current definitions including: death as the
cessation
of neural activity; death
as the cessation of blood circulation; death as the cessation of a combination
of bodily functions—respiration,
brain function, etc...
suicide—the intentional
act of taking or ending one’s own life. It is important to note the intent
of the
act. If a person does not
intend to end one’s own life, it is not suicide. In those cases without
intent it
might be considered an accident
or a tragedy.
The Philosophical Significance
of Death
There are many interesting
questions surrounding the concept of death. Metaphysically, what counts
as someone or a thing, being
‘dead’? If the body is dead, does that imply that all is gone and nothing
remains? Or, is there a
soul or spirit that survives, thus bodily death is not as significant?
Does
consciousness survive or
end with death? Epistemologically, is the neural definition the correct
one
or is the combination of
bodily functions the correct one? Ethically, is death something that should
be embraced or avoided?
Or, should we be agnostic on it?
The Philosophical Significance
of Suicide
The concept of suicide contains
a myriad of philosophical questions. Is one entitled to take one’s own
life?
Do we have obligations to
others that preclude us from taking our own lives? If we survive
the body, as
the dualist would argue,
can we be punished or rewarded for ending it? Is suicide a nobel act like
the
contemporary suicide bombers
believe? Should suicide be avoided at all costs as in contemporary
cases of active euthanasia,
leaving the person clinging to every moment of life?
The Readings
The Nagel piece, Death deals
with both topics, although suicide indirectly. Nagel offers a contemporary
look at death, which is
an interesting alternative to other conceptions.
Epictetus thinks that death
is not something to be avoided, nor embraced—one should be indifferent
(V,XIV, XVI). It should
govern how one lives his/her life (XXI). Suicide is an alternative for
those that are
fully rational, that is,
one should know enough to justify ending his/her life. The Stoics in general
had
a wide range of views on
suicide, some accepted it, others wanted no part of it.
Camus is against suicide
because it is an acceptance of the absurdity of the situation (64). You
must
recognize and struggle against
the Absurd (54). Death for the atheistic existentialists is the end—
there is no afterlife. Death
is something to be acknowledged as not of one’s own free will and as
something that one can do
a whole lot about (55).
Ayer offers no explicit thoughts
on suicide, but he does on death. We can understand that when Ayer
argues for a bodily-continuity
theory of personal identity, conjoined with his materialistic metaphysical
stance, when the body dies,
so does consciousness, (127). On suicide, Ayer would probably appeal
to psychology for an explanation—it
is not a philosophical problem.
Lecture 6: Epictetus on
Death/Suicide
(adapted from Preston and
the Enchiridion)
“The adherent would be provided
with certain practical thought experiments or physical activities designed
to implant and reinforce
the desired principles into his mind (or spirit). Among many examples from
Epictetus
are the following:
1) Examining passers-by,
making an observation about them, and then asking yourself whether the
content
of that
observation lies within the moral purpose. If it does not, it is to be
abandoned.
2) Applying the same technique
to news that is reported to us.
3) While kissing your child
goodnight, whisper to yourself “tomorrow you will die.”
4) Going through the inventory
of “things” in one’s life by starting with the most trifling (e.g., a cup)
and
advancing
to the most treasured (e.g., one’s child). With each item, consider it
carefully and then “cast
these
things away from you.”
5) Anticipating possible
unpleasant aspects of intended activities so as to diminish the effect
of the
aspect
should it occur (e.g., anticipating being splashed and jostled at a public
bath).
The point of all such exercises
is to train oneself to adopt certain attitudes and make certain judgments.
The nature of the training
is designed such that through constant repetition, the desired response
becomes
second-nature to the adherent.”
(Preston 16)
V. Men are disturbed not
by the things which happen, but by the opinions about the things: for example,
death is nothing terrible,
for if it were, it would have seemed so to Socrates; for the opinion about
death
that it is terrible is the
terrible thing. When, then, we are impeded or disturbed or grieved, let
us never
blame others, but ourselves,
that is our opinions.
5. "What upsets people is
not things themselves but their judgments about the things. For example,
death
is nothing dreadful (or
it would have appeared dreadful to Socrates), but instead the judgment
about death
that is dreadful--that is
what is dreadful. So, when we are thwarted or upset or distressed, let
us never blame
someone else but rather
ourselves, that is, our own judgments."
Socrates views on death
from the Apology.
“Death is one of two things:
Either it is annihilation and the dead have no consciousness of anything,
or it
is really a change—a migration
of the soul from this place to another. Now if there is no consciousness
but
only a dreamless sleep,
death must be a marvelous gain…If death is like this, then I call it gain,
because the
whole of time, if you look
at it in this way, can be regarded as no more than one single night.”
“If on the other hand death
is a removal from here to some other place, and if what we are told is
true, then
all dead are there, what
greater blessing could be than this, gentlemen? …one will find true judges
there who
are beyond our reaches of
so-called justice, and what of Homer and Orpheus? How much would you give
to
meet them? I would die ten
times over if this account is true…And above all gentlemen I should like
to spend
my time there questioning
and examining and searching people’s minds to find out who is wise among
them,
and who only thinks he is.”
You too gentlemen of the
jury, must look forward to death with confidence, and fix your minds on
this one
true belief, which is certain—nothing
can harm a good man in either life or death…”
So, Socrates views on
death are: 1) It would be the best night’s sleep ever, so why not embrace
it.
2) If the soul did live
on, he would be with greatness and be able to do what he did on earth with
these
great ones, for he was
a virtuous man as well. For Socrates then being sentenced to death for
crimes
he didn’t commit was
a good thing. Death held no grip on him and Epictetus’ point is that if
anyone had
a right to view death
as a bitter end—an innocent man being sentenced to death, Socrates did—but
he didn’t.
XI. Never say about anything,
I lost it, but say I have restored it. Is your child dead? It has
been restored.
Is your wife dead? She has
been restored. Has your estate been taken from you? Has this then not also
been restored? But he who
has taken it from me is a bad man. But what is it to you, by whose hands
the
giver demanded it back?
So as long as he may allow you, take care of it as a thing which belongs
to another,
as travelers do with their
inn.
11. "Never say about anything,
"I have lost it," but instead "I have given it back." Did your child die?
It was
given back. Did your wife
die? She was given back. "My land was taken." So this too was given back.
"But
the person who took it was
bad!" How does the way the giver(God/cosmos) concern you? As long as he
gives it, take of it as
something that is not your own, just as travelers treat an inn."
What is restoration/giving
back? You are returning it back to nature and the cosmic soul. You are
returning
your wife or child back
to nature. You’ve lost nothing, you’ve only returned what wasn’t yours.
XIV. If you wish your children
and your wife and your friends to live forever, you are silly; for you
would have
the things not in your power
to be in your power, and things which belong to others to be yours…
14. "You are foolish if you
want your children and your wife and your friends to live forever, since
you are
wanting things to be up
to you that are not up to you, and things to be yours that are not yours…"
Death is not in your power,
you cannot control the lifespan of your loved one’s, so you must adopt
the proper
attitude
towards it.
XXI. Let death and exile
and every other thing which appears dreadful be daily before your eyes;
but most of
all death:
and you will never think of anything mean nor will you desire anything
extravagantly.
21. "Let death and exile,
and everything that is terrible appear before your eyes everyday, especially
death;
and you
will never have anything contemptible in your thoughts or crave anything
excessively."
From Preston, we know
that 5 explains why Epictetus wants us to concentrate on death. By anticipating
it,
it
loses its control over you. The more you consider it, the less you will
be affected by it.
XXVI. We may learn the will
of nature from the things in which we do not differ from one another; for
instance,
when you neighbor’s slave
has broken his cup, or anything else, we are ready to say forthwith, that
it is one
of the things which happen.
You must know, then, that when your cup is also broken, you ought to think
as
you did when your neighbor’s
cup was broken. Transfer this reflection to greater things also. Is another
man’s
child or wife dead? There
is no one who would not say, this is an event incident to man (or this
is a common
event for all men). But
when a man’s own child or wife is dead, forthwith he calls out, Woe to
me, how wretched
I am. But we ought to remember
how we feel when we hear that it has happened to others.
26. "Is it possible to learn
the will of nature from the things in which we do not differ from each
other. For
example, when someone else's
little slave boy breaks his cup we are ready to say, "It's one of those
things
that just happen." Certainly,
then, when your own cup is broken you should be just the way you were when
the other person's was broken.
Transfer the same idea to larger matters. Someone else's child is dead,
or
his wife. There is no one
would not say, "It's the lot of a human being." But when one's own son
dies,
immediately it is, "Alas!
Poor me!" But we should have remembered how we feel when we hear the same
thing about others."
This is an example of
Preston 4. You go through an inventory of what you hold dear. You start
with the
most minimal thing and
go to the thing of greatest importance. What this teaches you is stoic
detachment.
You detach yourself emotionally
from the situations. You take a rational perspective—the cup is the same
as my child which is
the same as my wife. You don’t cry when you break a cup, thus you shouldn’t
cry when
your wife dies. Notice
the switch here from the first person (Woe to me…) to the third person
perspective
(But we ought to remember
how we feel…). Epictetus wants us to adopt a third person perspective on
our
events. Stoic detachment
then is just assuming a third person perspective on events and making a
judgment
from that perspective.
XVI. When you see a person
weeping in sorrow either when a child goes abroad or when he is dead…take
care that the appearance
do not hurry you away with it, as if he were suffering in external things.
But
straightway make a distinction
in your own mind, and be in readiness to say, it is not that which has
happened
that afflicts this man,
for it does afflict another, but it is the opinion about this thing which
afflicts the man. So
far as words, then, do not
be unwilling to show sympathy (sympathize with him verbally), and even
if it happens
so, to lament with him.
But take care that you do not lament internally also.
16. "When you see someone
weeping in grief at the departure of his child or the loss of his property,
take
care not to be carried away
by the appearance that the externals he is involved in are bad, and be
ready to
say immediately, "What weighs
down on this man is not what has happened (since it does not weigh down
on
someone else), but his judgment
about it." Do not hesitate, however, to sympathize with him verbally, and
even
to moan with him if the
occasion arises; but be careful not to moan inwardly."
Epictetus is often charged
with having a theory that doesn’t allow compassion. However, this passage
clearly
shows that he did. He
says to grieve with the man if necessary, but don’t let the grieving affect
you internally.
You would then be letting
an external affect you. If the man were to change his opinion about death,
he wouldn’t
need to grieve…
“But, to sum it all up: remember
that the door has been thrown open. Do not become a greater coward than
the children, but just as
they say, ‘I won’t play any longer,’ when the thing does not please them,
so do you
also, when things seem to
you to have reached that stage, merely say, ‘I won’t play any longer,’
and take
your departure; but if you
stay, stop lamenting.” (Epictetus, Discourses, I.25. pp. 153-155).
These are Epictetus’ thoughts
on suicide. When you have reached the point where life is no longer pleasing
to you, the correct act
is to either end your life or stop complaining. What Epictetus thought
was that if you
are a rational person,
a philosopher, and you had enough knowledge to know that dying was better
than living,
suicide is justifiable.
In other words, you need to do it for the right reason and not the wrong
one—externals
are ruling your life.
Lecture 6: Thomas Nagel’s,
Death
(adapted and edited from
David Banach’s, Death)
I. The Problem of Death.
If we believe that death is the permanent end of our conscious existence, is it a bad thing?
“”If death is the unequivocal
and permanent end of our existence, the question arises whether it is a
bad
thing
to die.”(1)
II. Two possible positions.
A. Death
deprives of us life which is essential quality we all we have. Therefore,
it is the greatest of all
losses because we lose something essential to our being.
“..life
is all we have and the loss of it is the greatest loss we can sustain.”(1)
B. Death
is the end of the subject. It is a mere blank, without a positive or negative
value. There is no
subject left to experience the value.
“ …and
that if we realize that death is not an unimaginable condition of the persisting
person, but a mere
blank, we will see that it can have no value whatever, positive or
negative.”(1)
III. Definitions
A. Death—permanent death, unsupplemented by any form of conscious survival.
B. Evil—deprivation of some quality or characteristic.
IV. If death is an evil,
it is not because of its positive features, but because of what it deprives
us of.
Namely,
the essential quality of life.
A. Life
has value apart from its contents. When we take away all the good and bad
experiences in life
what is left over, the bare experience of life, is valuable in itself.
“There
are elements which, if added to one’s experience, make life better; there
are other elements which,
if added to one’s experience, make life worse. But what remains when these
are set aside is not merely
neutral: it is emphatically positive…The additional positive weight is
supplied by experience itself, rather
than by any of its contents.”(2)
1. The value of life does not attach to mere organic survival. Surviving
in a coma does not appeal to us
as a form of living.
2. The good of life can be multiplied by time. More is better than less.
The quantities need not be
continuous. Much like Camus' point about the quantity versus quality of
experiences.
B. The state of being dead, or nonexistent, is not evil in itself. It cannot be what makes death bad.
“…But
if death is an evil, it is the loss of life, rather than the state of being
dead, or non-existent, or
unconscious, that is objectionable.” (3)
1. Death is not an evil that one accumulates more of the longer one is dead.
“Death, however, is not an evil of which Shakespeare has so far received
a larger portion than
Proust. If death is a disadvantage, it is not easy to say when a man suffers
it.” (3)
2. We would not regard a temporary suspension of life as a great misfortune in itself.
“If it ever happens that people can be frozen without reduction of the
conscious lifespan, it will be
inappropriate to pity those who are temporarily out of circulation.” (3)
3. We don't regard the long period of time before we were born, in which
we did not exist, as a great
misfortune.
“…none of existed before we were born (or conceived), but few regard that as a misfortune.” (3)
V. Three objections.
A. It
can be doubted that anything can be an evil unless it causes displeasure.
How can a deprivation of
life be an evil unless someone minds the deprivation?
B. In
the case of death there is no subject left. How can it be a misfortune
if there is no subject of the
misfortune? Who suffers the misfortune?
C. How can the period of nonexistence after our death be bad, if the period before our birth is not bad?
VI. Replies to the objections.
A. The
good or ill fortune of a person depends on a person’s history and possibilities
rather than just their
momentary state. Therefore a terrible misfortune can befall a person even
though they are not around to
experience the misfortune.
“Often we need to know his history to tell whether something is a misfortune
or not; this applies to ills like
deterioration,
deprivation and damage. Sometimes his experiential state is relatively
unimportant—as in
the case
of a man who wastes his life in the cheerful pursuit of a method of communicating
with asparagus
plants.”(5)
1. We consider ourselves to have been injured when someone acts against
our wishes or interests,
even when we are not aware of his or her actions.
“Loss, betrayal, deception, and ridicule are on this view bad because people
suffer when they
learn of them.”(5)
2. The discovery of wrongs done us in our absence make us unhappy because
they are misfortunes.
They are not misfortunes only because they made us unhappy when we discovered
them.
“For the natural view is that the discovery of betrayal makes us unhappy
because it is bad
to be betrayed— not that betrayal is bad because its discovery makes us
unhappy.”(5)
3. We consider a person who has suffered a severe brain injury, to have
a grave misfortune,
even though they may be quite happy in their new condition. We recognize
this only when we
consider the person he could be now.
“Such a development would be widely regarded as a severe misfortune, not
only for his friends
and relations, or for society, but also, and primarily for the person himself….there
is some doubt,
in fact, whether he can be said to exist any longer.” (5-6)
B. Although
the person as a subject does not survive his or her death, it can still
be the subject of the
misfortune.If he or she had not died, it would have gone on enjoying whatever
good there is in living.
“He has lost his life, and if he had not died, he would have continued
to live it, and to possess whatever
good there is in living.”(7)
C. The
period of time after death is time that death deprives us of. This is not
true of the period of
non-existence before birth. This explains the differences in our attitudes
towards these two periods
of non-existence.
“Therefore any death entails the loss of some life that its victim would
have led had he not died at
that or any earlier point. We know perfectly well what it would be for
him to have had it instead of
losing it, and there is no difficulty in identifying the loser.” (8)
D. The direction of time is important.
“Distinct possible lives of a single person can diverge from a common beginning,
but they cannot
converge to a common conclusion from diverse beginnings. (The latter would
represent not a set of
different possible lives of one individual, but a set of distinct set of
possible individuals, whose lives have
identical conclusions.) Given an identifiable individual, countless possibilities
for his continued existence
are imaginable, and we can clearly conceive of what it would be for him
to go on existing indefinitely.
However inevitable it is that this will not come about, its possibility
is still that of the continuation of a
good for him, if life is the good we take it to be.” (8)
VII. The question still remains
whether the non-realization of the possibility for further life is always
a
misfortune,
or whether this depends on what can naturally be hoped for.
A. Perhaps
we can only regard as a misfortune those deprivations which add gratuitously
to the inevitable
evils
we must endure. In this case, only premature death would be a great evil.
“Even if we can dispose of the objections against admitting misfortune
that is not experienced, or
cannot be assigned to a definite time in that person’s life, we still have
to set some limits on how
possible a possibility must be for its non-realization to be a misfortune
(or good fortune, should the
possibility be a bad one). The death of Keats at 24 is generally regarded
as tragic, that of Tolstoy at
82 is not. Although they will both be dead forever, Keat’s death deprived
him of many years of life which
were allowed to Tolstoy; so in a clear sense Keat’s loss was greater.”(9)
B. Whether
we see death as a deprivation depends upon the point of view we take up.
Nagel’s point is
whether or not we consider something from a personal or impersonal
point of view.
1. Observed from the outside, objectively, a human being cannot live much
more than 100 years.
From this point of view, we can only feel deprived of those years which
are allotted to beings of our type,
but which we do not live long enough to enjoy.
This is an impersonal POV. Remember the Tolstoy and Keats example.
2. When looked at in terms of our own experience, subjectively, our life
experience seems open ended.
We can see no reason why our normal experiences cannot continue indefinitely.
On this view death, no
matter how inevitable, is the cancellation of an indefinitely extendible
good. The fact that death is inevitable
does not affect how it feels in our experience to look forward to the end
of our experience.
This is a personal POV.
“If there is no limit to the amount of life that it would be good to have,
then it may be that a bad
end is in store for us all.” (10)