Lecture 15: Philosophy of Religion--Strong Theism
Instructor: Scott Dixon
(adapted from Wall's Thinking Critically About Philosophical Problems)

The Differences Between Religion, Theology, and Philosophy
        Religion and Theology--beliefs about the nature and existence of God are  accepted on faith,
            and ultimately authority.
        Philosophy--beliefs about the nature and existence of God must come from from experience
            and reason--which is based upon human knowledge.
        One way of distinguishing between the two might best be understood in the
            following way:

               naturalistic--philosophical explanations must comport with the existing
                    reality in some strong sense.
               anti-naturalistic--religious and theological explanations do not need to
                    comport with the same strength because they often appeal to super-
                    natural elements that are not based in reality for further justification.

Philosophy of Religion Lexicon
        Theism--the belief that a personal God exists.
        Deism--the belief that an impersonal God exists.
        Monotheism--the belief that only one God exists.
        Polytheism--the belief that more than one God exists.
        Atheism--the belief that God does not exist.
        Agnosticism--the belief that we are unable to know about the existence  and nature of God.
        Anthropormorphism--the belief that God has human form or properties.

The Concept of God
    God as a perfect being.
        1. Infinite
            a. eternal--no temporal limits, there was never a time God did not exist.
            b. omnipresent--no spatial limits, there is no place where God is not.
                    If God is everywhere, there can be no physical body because that would limit in
                        time and space.
        2. Creator
            a. God creates all and out of nothing.
                1. transcendent--totally distinct from the realm of time and space.
                2. ruler--God rules the creation or what he has acted upon.
            b. self-existent--God makes everything, although God is neither made nor created.
                He is the uncreated creator.
        3. Person
            a. God is thought of with personal characteristics such as being able to understand and can communicate.
        4. Good
            a. God is morally good and does no evil. Everything God does is morally correct.
            b. God is the highest good and the goal of our lives of what we should strive for even
                    though it may be unattainable.
        5. Omnipotent
            a. God is all powerful
            b. God is limited by the laws of logic; thus, God cannot make a squared circle.
            c. God does what is logically possible.
        6. Omniscient
            a. God knows all--past, present, and future.
            b. There is nothing that is not known by God.

    Some philosophers of the ancient and medieval times added two more characteristics a perfect being should have.

       7. Immutable
            a. Perfect beings cannot change.
            b. There is a medieval debate about the immutability of God.
                The debate is about the creation of the universe. It seems to me that what
                the group of Aristotelians failed to take into account is that if God does 'x', and 'x'
                is consistent with with His nature, then he has not changed. God is bound
                by logical impossibility and decreeing the world to come into existence is
                not a logical impossibility.
        8. Impassible
            a. God is unaffected by creatures like us.
            b. For God to be God, God has no wants or needs.

The Implications of 1-8
        1-8 express either one of two types of properties.
        Essential properties are those that something without that property fails to be that thing.
            For example, an essential property of being human is having DNA. An essential
                property of water is H2O.
       Relational properties are those that put a thing in relation to another thing. For example,
            'x taller than y', 'y is heavier than z', and many others. God being the ruler of the world
            is a relational property, it puts him into a relation with an object. However God is
            not dependent upon that object, nor does that property form an essential property of
            God. In other words, God could not be ruler of the world and still be God. However
            God could not be omnipotent and still be God which is an essential property.

The properties we deem to be essential constitute our concept of God.
        Implication#1--essential properties often conflict and reveal  inconsistencies.
            a. If God is all good and cannot perform an immoral action, then
                    there is something that God cannot do (this conflicts with omnipotence).
            b. If God cannot do things that are logically impossible, then there
                    is something God cannot do. The stronger claim is that if God
                    is bound by the laws of logic he created them knowing they
                    would limit him. But, before the laws of logic existed, nothing
                    was logically impossible, so God knowingly limited his own power.
            c. If God is outside of time, how does he operate in time?
            d. If God is everywhere, then he is in and outside of time. If he is
                inside time, he must be limited in some sense and this conflicts
                with his being unlimited.
        Implication#2--properties can be ambiguous--more than one meaning.
            a. What does 'time' mean for God? Is it sequential or momentary?
            b. What does 'eternal' mean? Existed forever, existed?
        Implication#3--
            a. What 1 and 2 show is a semantic problem. When absolute
                statements are used, they can conflict with each other. Having
                7-8 absolute statements further magnifies the problem. The
                question becomes, does our language limit an unlimited God?
                The 20th century Austrian philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein once said,
                "The limits of my language are the limits of my world." Our world is
                not entirely coextensive with God's, thus our limits may be just
                our limits and not God's.

We began by examining our basic belief that God exists.
        The next step is to formulate the problem.

    What is the reasonable thing to believe about the existence of God?

 So, we are now looking for solutions to this question. we might also use the method of
    reversal to get at one of many solutions by reformulating the question,

     Why might belief in God not be a reasonable thing?

     Fideism--An emotional commitment to the existence of God and not a rational
        commitment based upon reasons and evidence.

      Soren Kierkegaard--rational knowledge was the enemy of God and to truly
            know God, one must have complete and utter devotion through trust. When
            you try to rationalize God, you are not trusting Him. Trust comes first, then rationalization.

        "201. All this world--historical to-do and argument and proofs of the truth of
            Christianity must be discarded; there only proof there is, is Faith. If I truly
            have a conviction, my conviction to me is always stronger than reasons;
            actually a conviction is what supports the reasons, not the other way
            around."  Diary of Soren Kierkegaard, p. 163

      Kierkegaard's version of fideism is extreme. There are lesser versions including
                St. Augustine's fides proecedit intellectum, or faith precedes understanding
                is another version. Augustine's point was that one put the intellect aside and
                give faith the highest priority. St. Anselm's credo ut intelligam,  or I believe in
                order that I may understand, is another version. This serves as the basis
                for his Ontological Argument for the existence of God.

The Ontological Argument (from Sober, Core Questions, pp. 82-83)
        History: Originally formulated by Saint Anselm (1033-1109). Anselm was a
        Catholic theologian and eventually became the Archbishop of Canterbury. The
        argument is found in the Proslogion. Rene Descartes (1596-1650) a French
        philosopher and mathematician also used several versions of the ontological
        argument that can be found in his Meditations on First Philosophy.

        O1--By definition God is the greatest possible being.
        O2--A being who fails to exist in the actual physical world we inhabit, while
                existing in other possible worlds, is less perfect than a being who exists
                in all possible worlds.
        ------------------------------------------------
        Thus, God necessarily exists.

The Cosmological Argument (from Sober, Core Questions, pp. 38-39)
        History: Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274) is the most famous proponent, but arguably
        a form of the argument can be traced back to Aristotle and his Prime Mover
        argument. Contemporary proponents include William Lane Craig with a unique
        version called the Kalam Cosmological Argument. His argument is based upon
        the work of an medieval Islamic scholar named Al-Ghazali (1058-1111).

    Aquinas's First Argument from Motion
        M1--There are objects in the natural world that are in motion.
        M2--Objects that are in motion in the natural world are always sent into motion
                by objects other than themselves.
        M3--Causes in the natural world must precede their effects.
        M4--There are no infinite cause/effect chains in the natural world.
        ------
        M5--Thus, there is an entity outside of the natural world (a super natural being)
                which causes the motion of the first moving object that exists in the natural
                world.
        ------
        Thus, God exists.

Aquinas's Second Argument from Causality
        C1--There are events in the natural world.
        C2--In the natural world, every event has a cause, and no event is caused by
                itself.
        C3--Causes must precede their effects in the natural world.
        C4--In the natural world, there are no cause/effect chains that are infinite.
        ------
        C5--Thus, there is an entity outside of nature (a supernatural being), which
                causes the first event that occurs in the natural world.
        -----
        Thus, God exists.

 Paley's Design Argument
        History: William Paley (1743-1805) was an English theologian and moral
        philosopher. A contemporary proponent of this view is William Dembski.

        D1--Organisms are well suited to the tasks of survival and reproduction.
        D2--Organisms are intricate.
        ----------
        ---------
        Thus, organisms were created by intelligent design.

  Parallel Argument
        W1--The watch is well suited to the task of measuring time.
        W2--The watch is intricate.
        --------
        --------
        Thus, the watch was created by intelligent design.

Van Til and the Transcendental Argument
    History
        Born May 3, 1895 in Holland.
        Awarded a Th.M. from Princeton Seminary in 1925.
        Awarded a Ph.D. in 1927 from Princeton University in
        Philosophy for his dissertation God and the Absolute.
        Wrote over 30 books and 220 articles/reviews on Christianity, Philosophy, Ethics and Theology.
        He died in 1987 after teaching from 1929-1972 at  Westminister Seminary.

Calvinism versus Arminianism
Calvinism                               v.                   Arminianism
T—Total Depravity                                Limited Depravity
(man is bad due to sin)                                (man is good and bad)
U—Unconditional Election                   Conditional Election
(God saves who He choses to)                     (man saves himself)
L—Limited Atonement                         Unlimited Atonement
(Christ died for the Elect)                                (Christ died for all)
I—Irresistible Grace                             Resistible Grace
(God’s grace cannot be resisted)                 (Man can resist God’s grace)
P—Perseverance of the Saints             No Perseverance
(God will keep you in the faith)                (Man can lose faith and salvation)

Van Til was a strong Calvinist. Notice for the Calvinist, God does it all. For the Arminian, he/she
is in charge and God more or less becomes his/her servant—God does not do it all, man either
does it or “cooperates” with God.

Why I Believe in God
This is a simple pamphlet showing the transcendental method. The transcendental method
is defined as “Transcendental reasoning is concerned to discover what general conditions
must be fulfilled for any particular instance of knowledge to be possible: it has been central
to the philosophies…of Aristotle and Kant. Van Til asks what view of man, mind, truth,
language, and the world is necessarily presupposed by our conception of knowledge and
our methods of pursuing it.” (Bahnsen 5-6) Another way you might want to think about this
is what kind of structure makes man, mind, truth, and language possible at all—as a coherent
entity that produces knowledge.

Five Main Themes in Van Til
    1. Creature/Creator distinction. Man is created and necessarily relies upon his/her Creator.
        The Creator relies upon man in no way.
    2. Belief versus Unbelief. If one is not in a state of belief, they are in a state of unbelief.
        There is no middle ground.
    3. No Neutrality. There is no neutral worldview. Every single person has a worldview and they
        argue from it. The atheist has a worldview with metaphysical, epistemological, and ethical
        posits. The Christian does the same, as does the Buddhist, etc…
        There is no neutral worldview from which other worldviews can be judged.
    4. Sin Blinds. Van Til refers to this as wearing colored glasses. Going back to the ‘T’
        in Calvinism, Van Til believes that sin so utterly affects one’s thinking that they
        cannot see the simple evidences and truths of Christianity.
    5. Autonomy versus Theonomy—Man either believes himself to be his/her own law
        or he/she believes that he/she relies upon the Law of God and His Will.

The Transcendental Argument
    1) God is the All-Conditioner.
    2) If God is the All-Conditioner, then his/her experience is unified.
    3) Unification of experience gives experience meaning.
    ---------------------------------------------------------------------------
    C—God as the All Conditioner gives his/her experience meaning.

The Unintelligibility Argument
    1) Man is the All-Conditioner.
    2) If man is the All-Conditioner, then his/her experience is dis- unified.
    3) Experience that is disunified has no meaning.
    ---------------------------------------------------------------------------
    C—Man as the All-Conditioner gives his/her experience no meaning.

We need to analyze two quotes to understand what Van Til is doing in these
    two arguments.

“On the other hand, by my belief in God I do have unity in my experience. Not of
    course the sort of unity you want. Not a unity that is the result of my autonomous
    determination. But a unity that is higher than mine and prior to mine.”

 “Looking about me I see both order and disorder in every dimension of life. But I look
    at both of them in the light of the Great Creator who is back of them.”

Unity in experience—causal connections between events, conceptual continuity,
    logical necessity, moral absolutes and others. All of these unify my experience, I
    know that if I put gasoline on a fire it will flame up, I know the concept of ‘dog’ I
    have stays the same, it doesn’t change, I know that ‘tautologies’ will always
    be true, and I know that moral absolutes like “You should not murder” holds for all
    of us. Not only do these unify my particular experience, they unify yours as well.
    Van Til believes that only by presupposing God can we have this kind of unity.
    God is the All-Conditioner, he makes the unity of our experience possible. We are
    his Creatures in His Creation.

Without presupposing God, we have disunity. “Man by contrast either imposes his
    own unifying ideas of his own mind on an external reality not controlled by his
    mind.” This is form of epistemological subjectivism. “Or (man) respects the
    particularity and novelty of every fact in the world, in which case nothing can be
    said about it using unifying concepts or uniform principles. Imposing a ‘system’ in
    advance discards the need for scientific research; respecting the individuality and
    novelty of experience destroys the intelligibility of those facts in advance.” (B, 140)

Translation: There are two points here. 1) Man’s mind may impose unifying ideas on
    reality, however there is no guarantee that they unify reality. Thus his unification is
    not objective and there is no unification between the individual and reality. 2) If
    every fact in the world is unique, there is nothing to unify those facts because they
    share nothing in common. The science claim is interesting. This goes back to #1.
    If your subjective system gives you unity, why do you need science? Your system
    already limits your discovery because there is no necessary correspondence with
    reality. Your system tells you everything you need to know. The “individuality and
    novelty” claim of the last sentence is strong. If everything is an individual and
    unique in experience, why would we count those as facts? Facts require some kind
    of unification. Cal Poly is a university is a fact which requires unification of the
    concept of ‘university’, otherwise what would Cal Poly be? A school, once again that
    requires a unified concept. If you really want to push this argument to its strongest
    conclusion, there is just a sequence of experiences, all individual. Yet, this requires
    a unified concept of ‘experience’ and ‘individual.’

Summary: Four arguments for the existence of God have been presented. Three of them are
conceptual: ontological, cosmological, and transcendental. Two of them are empirical in some
sense: teleological and transcendental. A unique property of transcendental arguments is that
they are both conceptual (what are the necessary preconditions for experience) and empirical
(what is our experience actually like). These two should correspond. We also considered a
non-rational argument through the ideas of Kierkegaard called 'fideism.'
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

 Philosophy of Religion--Strong Atheism
Instructor: Scott Dixon

------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

A.J. Ayer: The Meaningless of Religious Language

 Ayer’s Arguments Against the Possibility of Religious Knowledge

    Argument#1

    The argument needs to be understood with the presupposition that premises for the
        existence of God are not certain.

        1) If the premise is empirical, then it is only probable.
        2) If the premise is a tautology/a priori, then it is certain.
        3) God cannot be deduced from a tautology/ a priori proposition.
        4) Premise (1) is not certain.
        5) Deductive arguments require certain premises.
        ------------------------------------------------------------------------
        C—Therefore there is not possible to demonstrate by deductive arguments that God exists.

    Translated: The conclusion follows if we take the prime mark of deduction to be that premises
logically guarantee the truth of a conclusion. This logical guarantee follows if the premises are
certain, so is the conclusion. However, by empirical premises aren’t certain so they can’t be used,
and God cannot be deduced from a tautology. So these two combined make it impossible to
demonstrate that God exists through a deductive argument.

    Argument #2

    Ayer next considers whether or not an argument can be given for the existence
        of God that is merely probable versus being certain.

        1) If the existence of God is probable, then the proposition that He exists
                would be empirical.
        2) Empirical manifestations of God do not equal a transcendent being.
        3) If the empirical manifestations are not equal to a transcendent being,
                then there is something not being defined empirically.
        4) If something cannot be fully defined empirically, then it is a
                metaphysical concept.
        ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------
        C—God is metaphysical concept and thus is not probable because
            probable concepts are capable of having a truth-value, something
            metaphysical concepts are not.

    Translation: The crucial premise here is (2). Ayer’s idea is that you can take a sum total of
physical manifestations of God, yet they will never equal the total concept of God. Or more
simply, a) # of physical manifestations + b) God’s other qualities that are not empirically
manifested = the total concept of God. However, since there is no (b) on Ayer’s account
(this is what cannot be defined empirically), there is no equivalency.

The previous then implies the concept of God being a metaphysical concept because it is not
fully definable empirically. And since empirical statements and tautologies are the only types
of meaningful statements, i.e. they are capable of having a truth- value, the metaphysical
statement including “God” has no truth-value.

Ayer on Religious Language

    Ayer’s view here is very fair about various positions on God.

    A) theism: God exists—a metaphysical statement
    B) atheism: God does not exist—a metaphysical statement
    C) agnostic: I don’t know if God exists—a metaphysical statement

    Since ‘God exists’ is a metaphysical statement, ‘God does not exist’ is one as well.
‘God exists’ does not have a truth-value, nor does ‘God does not exist.’ Agnosticism is the
view that either (A) or (B) is true, but that one does not know which is true. However, if (A)
and (B) are both metaphysical statements without truth-values, (C) will not have a truth-value
either. Thus all three are metaphysical statements that are neither true nor false.

God as a Proper Name

    Proper names denote individuals. ‘Scott W. Dixon’ denotes me and only me given a certain
history. Each proper name corresponds to an object. Ayer says, “ The mere existence of the
noun is enough to foster the illusion that there is a real, or at any rate a possible entity
corresponding to it. It is only when we inquire into what God’s attributes are that we discover
that ‘God,’ in this usage, is not a genuine name.”(116) Ayer’s point is that transcendent objects
and their attributes are not real in the empirical sense. For names to refer, it must be empirical;
thus, ‘God’ is not a genuine name because it fails to refer to an empirical object.

Religion and Science

Religious language does not express significant propositions; thus it is without a truth-
value. Scientific language does express significant propositions; thus it has a truth-value.
Scientific language and religious language have no common ground, thus they have no
relation to each other.

Ernest Nagel: Defending Atheism

   History: Nagel (1901-1985) was a philosopher of science with sympathies for the
    Logical Positivist Movement. He taught at Columbia and might best be known for
    his popular book called "Godel's Proof" which explained the nature of Godel's
    Incompleteness Theorems in an understandable way to a broad audience. Among
    hisother works are An Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method (with M. R.Cohen,
    1934), Sovereign Reason (1954), Logic without Metaphysics (1957), The Structure of
    Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation (1961), and Observation
    and Theory in Science (with others, 1971).

Defending Atheism

This paper contains two major sections. There is a negative section where Nagel criticizes
classical arguments for the existence of God. Following that, he goes on to provide a positive
section on why he believes atheism might be true. One other thing you want to notice about
this paper is the way he sets it up. This paper is a prime example of how to write philosophy:
1) He begins by defining his terms (p.139); 2) He then discusses what follows from those
definitions (pp. 139-140); 3) He further clarifies a particular conception of atheism that he is
interested in (p. 140); and the begins his critique. 1-3 set the foundation for his critique to come
forth in a meaningful way.

    Nagel on the Cosmological Argument

    1. Every event must have a cause.
    2. Event C must have been caused by event B which must have been caused by event A....
        (this a backwards progression).
    3. 2 entails an infinite progression.
    4. An infinite progression of an actual series of events is unintelligible.
    C--Thus there must be a first cause who is God to save intelligibility.

    Critique #1: He is not concerned with the truthfulness of premise 1.
    1. Every event must have a cause.
    2. God does not need a cause because He is self-caused.
    3. If God is self-caused, then there is no reason the world is not self-caused.
    C--There is no reason the world is not self-caused.

    Critique #2: He challenges premise 4 by appealing to modern mathematical
    conceptions of infinity. I suspect he is drawing up Cantor's Diagonal Proof where
    the set of real numbers (rational and irrational numbers) is larger than the set of
    integers (or rational numbers), that is, the uncountably infinite set of real numbers
    is "larger" than the countably infinite set of integers and thus cannot be put into a
    one-one correspondence. The parallel comes in when we consider the notions of
    uncountably and countably. If you can't count the events and causes, then it is not
    clear why you need a first cause. The notion of uncountably lets in there being no
    necessary beginning, nor a necessary end. And if this is the case, you don't God
    for the beginning or the end of time or creation. Thus Nagel's point is that the
    cosmological argument presupposes a finite progression whereas not only is
    an infinite progression intelligible, and infinite progression that is uncountable
    is intelligible given Cantor's proof. Thus, he disputes premise 4.

    Nagel on the Ontological Argument

    1. If God is omnipotent, then He is a perfect being.
    2. A perfect being is one whose nature is perfect and complete in every respect.
    3. If we have the idea of a perfect being, we have just defined it.
    C--God must exist by definition because we have the idea of God as a perfect being.

    Why? By premise 2, if God failed to exist He would not be complete nor perfect.
    He would lack an attribute or quality of His nature.

    Critique: Drawing upon Kant, Nagel focuses upon the word 'exist.' Kant would argue
    that premise 2 does not contain the attribute of 'existence.' Or to be succinct,
    existence is not an attribute. Take any idea you wish, does that idea entail that the
    content of that idea exist in reality? If we have the idea of a $100 bill, does that
    mean it exists in reality? We have the idea of a $100 bill but that is separate from
    it actually existing. Thus, God as one that is perfect and complete by definition does
    not entail that God exists in reality.

    We might think of this also in the following way. Remembering back to our issues
    in conceptual analysis there are questions of fact and questions of concept. It
    seems that what this argument draws upon is a confusion of concept and fact.
    Is God a perfect being? We may have the concept of God as a perfect being,
    yet there needs to be another argument for the fact of God. Does God exist? The
    argument builds existence into concept and in the process, turns a question of
    concept subtlety into a question of fact.

    Nagel on the Design Argument

        D1--Organisms are well suited to the tasks of survival and reproduction.
        D2--Organisms are intricate as is the environment in which they exist.
        D3--The intricacy did not happen by random chance nor accident; it was
            planned.
        ----------
        ---------
        Thus, organisms and their environment were created by intelligent design.

        Analogous Argument
        W1--The watch is well suited to the task of measuring time.
        W2--The watch is an intricate environment.
        W3--The intricacy did not happen by random chance nor accident; it was
            planned.
        --------
        --------
        Thus, the watch was created by intelligent design.

        The argument trades upon the arguments being alike: the world and the watch
        are alike in intricacy and planning. It is an argument by analogy.

    Critique: The argument is disanalogous because we never come across a watch
    that hasn't been made by somebody and 'being made' is different between biology
    and the watch. A watch is constructed from bare materials, but saying that
    organisms construct in the same way is false. My parents no more made me from
    scratch than yours did.

    Biological adaptation accounts for variations and selection of traits without appeal
    to an intelligent designer. Thus the complexity of biology is able to make sense of
    selection and survival, and in the process, gives a natural order where an
    intelligent design need not be appealed to for explanation.

    Nagel on Kant and the Mystics

    Kant: This is a moral argument for the existence of God. We need God to guarantee
    morality as something that is ideal. Without God grounding it, we have no reason to
    be virtuous or good.

    Critique: Postulating God has no guarantees and thus we have no way of knowing
    how what is good or being virtuous would be realized.

    Mystics: This is an experiential argument for the existence of God. I know God
    exists because I've have an intimate, subjective experience with Him. These
    feelings are then taken as a validation of the existence of a supernatural being.

    Critique: An experience is just that an experience. For experiences to have
    objective nature, they must be able to be verified under controlled conditions and
    be confirmed by independent observers. Otherwise, they are subjective and no
    further inferences are able to be justified, that is, arguing from an experience to
    the existence of something like God causing that experience.

    Nagel on Theodicy

    Theodicy--the problem of evil, how can an all-good God allow evil?

    Nagel believes that the very thesis of theism shows an incoherency between
    God's attributes of omnipotence, omniscience, and omnibenevolence and
    reconciling them with evil in the world. How can an all-powerful, all-knowing,
    and all-good God allow evil in the world? If God is all-powerful, why can't He get
    rid of evil? If God is all-knowing, why can't He know that evil conflicts with his other
    attributes? If God is all-good, how can He allow evil to exist when evil is the
    negation of good?

    Critique: Human history shows evil exists. It is not clear how a omnibenevolent
    being is revealed in this history because of the inconsistency. Thus, we have no
    reason to suppose an omnibenevolent being exists or has been at work in history.

Positive Atheism

    Nagel puts forth a few conceptions that are inherent to philosophical atheism. He is
    no longer criticizing theism at this point, but instead is drawing out a few general
    ideas that most philosophical atheists hold to.

    1. Non-physical entities like souls, do not exercise a causal effect on the material
        body. To achieve an understanding of what goes on in the universe, we must
        look to a naturalistic explanation. Bodies, matter, and the like are what we need
        to analyze.

    2. Empiricism is the way we achieve knowledge. "But there is substantial agreement
        among them that controlled sensory observation is the court of final appeal in
        issues concerning matters of fact."(146) The sciences can explain all that is
        empirical without reference to God or a Deity.

    3. Utilitarianism is the correct moral theory. Because it deals with actual human
        capacities and those in relation to others in society, it is the best standard
        for evaluating moral claims and judgments. Nagel notes this places man into
        a necessary relationship with others in society and all's well-being must be
        considered in contrast to the theistic model which is individualistic.

    Thus, in 1-3 we have naturalism, empiricism, and utilitarianism as the positive
    doctrine of atheism.

Summary: Both Ayer and Nagel argue strongly against atheism. One uses language as his
primary instrument, where as the other deals with traditional philosophical problems and
how they are answered.